Encyc

Encyc houses over 100 concepts relevant to the history of eugenics and its continued implications in contemporary life. These entries represent in-depth explorations of key concepts for understanding eugenics.

Aboriginal and Indigenous Peoples
Michael Billinger
Alcoholism and drug use
Paula Larsson
Archives and institutions
Mary Horodyski
Assimilation
Karen Stote
Bioethical appeals to eugenics
Tiffany Campbell
Bioethics
Gregor Wolbring
Birth control
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Childhood innocence
Joanne Faulkner
Colonialism
Karen Stote
Conservationism
Michael Kohlman
Criminality
Amy Samson
Degeneracy
Michael Billinger
Dehumanization: psychological aspects
David Livingstone Smith
Deinstitutionalization
Erika Dyck
Developmental disability
Dick Sobsey
Disability rights
Joshua St. Pierre
Disability, models of
Gregor Wolbring
Down Syndrome
Michael Berube
Education
Erna Kurbegovic
Education as redress
Jonathan Chernoguz
Educational testing
Michelle Hawks
Environmentalism
Douglas Wahlsten
Epilepsy
Frank W. Stahnisch
Ethnicity and race
Michael Billinger
Eugenic family studies
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenic traits
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics as wrongful
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics: positive vs negative
Robert A. Wilson
Family planning
Caroline Lyster
Farming and animal breeding
Sheila Rae Gibbons
Feeble-mindedness
Wendy Kline
Feminism
Esther Rosario
Fitter family contests
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Gender
Caroline Lyster
Genealogy
Leslie Baker
Genetic counseling
Gregor Wolbring
Genetics
James Tabery
Genocide
Karen Stote
Guidance clinics
Amy Samson
Hereditary disease
Sarah Malanowski
Heredity
Michael Billinger
Human enhancement
Gregor Wolbring
Human experimentation
Frank W. Stahnisch
Human nature
Chris Haufe
Huntington's disease
Alice Wexler
Immigration
Jacalyn Ambler
Indian--race-based definition
Karen Stote
Informed consent
Erika Dyck
Institutionalization
Erika Dyck
Intellectual disability
Licia Carlson
Intelligence and IQ testing
Aida Roige
KEY CONCEPTS
Robert A. Wilson
Kant on eugenics and human nature
Alan McLuckie
Marriage
Alexandra Minna Stern
Masturbation
Paula Larsson
Medicalization
Gregor Wolbring
Mental deficiency: idiot, imbecile, and moron
Wendy Kline
Miscegenation
Michael Billinger
Motherhood
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Natural and artificial selection
Douglas Wahlsten
Natural kinds
Matthew H. Slater
Nature vs nurture
James Tabery
Nazi euthanasia
Paul Weindling
Nazi sterilization
Paul Weindling
Newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Nordicism
Michael Kohlman
Normalcy and subnormalcy
Gregor Wolbring
Parenting and newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Parenting of children with disabilities
Dick Sobsey
Parenting with intellectual disabilities
David McConnell
Pauperism
Caroline Lyster
Person
Gregor Wolbring
Physician assisted suicide
Caroline Lyster
Political science and race
Dexter Fergie
Popular culture
Colette Leung
Population control
Alexandra Stern
Prenatal testing
Douglas Wahlsten
Project Prevention
Samantha Balzer
Propaganda
Colette Leung
Psychiatric classification
Steeves Demazeux
Psychiatry and mental health
Frank W. Stahnisch
Psychology
Robert A. Wilson
Public health
Lindsey Grubbs
Race and racialism
Michael Billinger
Race betterment
Erna Kurbegovic
Race suicide
Adam Hochman
Racial hygiene
Frank W. Stahnisch
Racial hygiene and Nazism
Frank Stahnisch
Racial segregation
Paula Larsson
Racism
Michael Billinger
Reproductive rights
Erika Dyck
Reproductive technologies
Caroline Lyster
Residential schools
Faun Rice
Roles of science in eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Schools for the Deaf and Deaf Identity
Bartlomiej Lenart
Science and values
Matthew J. Barker
Selecting for disability
Clarissa Becerra
Sexual segregation
Leslie Baker
Sexuality
Alexandra Minna Stern
Social Darwinism
Erna Kurbegovic
Sociobiology
Robert A. Wilson
Sorts of people
Robert A. Wilson
Special education
Jason Ellis
Speech-language pathology
Joshua St. Pierre
Standpoint theory
Joshua St. Pierre
Sterilization
Wendy Kline
Sterilization compensation
Paul Weindling
Stolen generations
Joanne Faulkner
Subhumanization
Licia Carlson
Today and Tomorrow: To-day and To-morrow book series
Michael Kohlman
Training schools for the feeble-minded
Katrina Jirik
Trans
Aleta Gruenewald
Transhumanism and radical enhancement
Mark Walker
Tuberculosis
Maureen Lux
Twin Studies
Douglas Wahlsten & Frank W. Stahnisch
Ugly Laws
Susan M. Schweik and Robert A. Wilson
Unfit, the
Cameron A.J. Ellis
Violence and disability
Dick Sobsey
War
Frank W. Stahnisch
Women's suffrage
Sheila Rae Gibbons

Human nature

The idea of human nature refers to the distinctive cluster of biologically inherited physical, behavioral, and psychological traits that characterize the natural human condition. Descriptions of some trait or other as part of human nature are often controversial, for three reasons: (1) there are disputes over what conditions need to be satisfied for something to count as “natural”; (2) claims about human nature are typically made without sufficient understanding of the hereditary basis of the traits in question, especially in the case of complex behavioral and psychological traits; (3) the identification of some human state as “natural” is seen as having ethical, social, and even legal implications. Eugenics can be understood as an attempt to induce changes in the cluster of traits that characterize human nature, promoting some traits and extinguishing others from the human population — just as the goal of farming and animal breeding is to generate a strain of organisms that reliably reproduces a certain cluster of desirable traits.

Naturalness
Physical, behavioral, and psychological traits take on different forms or states in different people. Some times these differences are enormous — for example, people differ with respect to their number of legs — but usually they are small, so small that we need measuring devices to detect them. One way to think of the naturalness of a physical, behavioral, or psychological state is by comparing it to the range of variation observed within the human population. Although there is some variation in the human population with respect to leg number, the range of variation is very narrow. Moreover, the state of having two legs occurs with a much higher frequency than any other state in that range. On one conception of naturalness, having two legs is a natural human state because it occurs with sufficient frequency. Having more or less than two legs is an unnatural human state because it is extraordinarily uncommon.

In principle, this way of understanding natural human states can be applied to behavioral and psychological traits. Just as we would conclude that having two legs is natural for humans because it is so common, we can sort natural from unnatural behavior by observing the relative frequencies with which each behavior occurs. Alas, humans exhibit an extensive range of behavioral variation. As the range of variation expands, inferences concerning the naturalness of a given behavioral state become more and more difficult to justify. Because so many people act and think in so many different ways, it is difficult to identify particular behaviors that achieve a relative frequency that is high enough to allow us to infer naturalness with the same degree of confidence as having two legs provides. This problem persists even when we subdivide the human population into smaller classes, such as man, woman, child, etc. In response to this basic fact about human behavioral and psychological variation, many have argued that there is no such thing as human nature, because there is no cluster of behavioral and psychological traits that occurs with sufficient frequency to be considered “normal” from a statistical standpoint (Hull 1986).

Statistical frequency is not the only method by which to approach the distinction between natural and unnatural human behavior and psychology. In some instances, what has been identified as the “natural” human state turns out to be nothing more than what is desirable to the person or group engaged in making the distinction, and what is “unnatural” turns out to be merely what is undesirable from that group’s perspective. It is not plausible to think that every identification of a human state as “natural” works this way, but history suggests that the practice is common enough to proceed with caution. Many societies (e.g Nazi Germany) have held marriages between individuals of different racial or ethnic groups (see miscegenation) to be unnatural for reasons that are now known to have been rooted exclusively in the subjective preferences of some group or other. Historically, the classification of certain behavioral or psychological conditions as pathological has also been susceptible to the intrusion of personal opinions concerning which sorts of people are desirable and which are undesirable.

Nature vs Nurture
The theory and practice of eugenics is founded on the presumption that the range of variation in human behavior and psychology can be manipulated by selective breeding in the manner of farming and animal breeding. In order for such a program to work, differences in the behaviors targeted for selective manipulation would have to be caused by genetic differences. In addition, those genetic differences would have to be hereditary. For example, were we to target jealousy -- an alleged aspect of human nature (Buss 2000) -- for elimination from the population through selective human breeding, our success would require that differences between individuals with respect to their propensity toward jealousy be in part attributable to genetic differences, and that those genetic differences be passed down from parent to child. Because the genetic bases for most human physical, psychological, and behavioral characteristics are unknown, it is plausible that many of the aspects of the human condition normally attributed to an intrinsic human nature are overwhelmingly, or at least significantly, the product of environmental influence on human development, psychology, or behavior. This, in turn, makes it difficult to know for any particular characteristic whether it satisfies the conditions required to manipulate its frequency through selective breeding.

Ethical Dimensions of Human Nature
One reason for the controversy surrounding assignments of some behavior as “natural” is the fact that perceptions of a trait’s naturalness affect our moral assessment of that trait. Historically, these moral assessments have frequently had legal or policy implications. Violent actions that are considered natural behavioral responses — for example, so-called “crimes of passion” — are often treated more leniently by the justice system than actions that do not enjoy “natural” status.

-Chris Haufe

  • Buss, David (2000). The Dangerous Passion: Why Jealousy Is as Necessary as Love and Sex. New York: Free Press.

  • Hull, David L. (1986). “On Human Nature.” PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association Vol. 1986, Volume Two: Symposia and Invited Papers (1986), pp. 3-13.

  • Downes and Machery (2013), eds. Arguing about Human Nature: Contemporary Debates. New York: Routledge.

  • Kronfeldner, Maria, Neil Roughley, and Georg Toepfer. 2014. “Recent Work on Human Nature: Beyond Traditional Essences.” Philosophy Compass 9 (9): 642–52.